Philosophy – Rational Standard https://rationalstandard.com Free political commentary for the dissenting South African Tue, 14 Nov 2017 20:09:48 +0000 en-GB hourly 1 https://wordpress.org/?v=4.8.3 https://i2.wp.com/rationalstandard.com/wp-content/uploads/2012/01/cropped-RS-Logo.png?fit=32%2C32&ssl=1 Philosophy – Rational Standard https://rationalstandard.com 32 32 94510741 Reflections on Ayn Rand’s ‘Atlas Shrugged’ https://rationalstandard.com/reflections-ayn-rands-atlas-shrugged/ https://rationalstandard.com/reflections-ayn-rands-atlas-shrugged/#comments Sun, 29 Oct 2017 22:01:27 +0000 https://rationalstandard.com/?p=6680 Tuesday, 10 October 2017, marked the 60th anniversary of the publication of Ayn Rand’s Atlas Shrugged. The novel was Rand’s fourth, and longest, work, and laid the groundwork for what would become the philosophy she formulated: Objectivism. As of 2010, 7,000,000 copies of the novel had been sold since 1957. While themes such as capitalism, […]

The post Reflections on Ayn Rand’s ‘Atlas Shrugged’ appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
Tuesday, 10 October 2017, marked the 60th anniversary of the publication of Ayn Rand’s Atlas Shrugged. The novel was Rand’s fourth, and longest, work, and laid the groundwork for what would become the philosophy she formulated: Objectivism.

As of 2010, 7,000,000 copies of the novel had been sold since 1957. While themes such as capitalism, free speech, and individualism are present, the novel is based on Rand’s view of man’s mind, and the role thereof.

Atlas Shrugged is set in a United States in which more and more “men of the mind”, creative people, go on strike because of the prevailing philosophy – altruism – chipping away at them and their lives. The productive and successful are vilified and the only way to ‘grow’ business is through government deals and influence. When characters such as Hank Rearden, Dagny Taggart, and Franciso d’Anconia go on strike, Rand presents the consequences of the producers withholding their minds from society – the need of others is no longer a hold on them to produce their innovations, art, business leadership, scientific research, entrepreneurship or wealth.

In Atlas Shrugged, Rand develops the philosophy of rational self-interest – the philosophical position that your own happiness ought to be the standard by which you live. No one, no matter their social or economic position, has a moral claim on your mind, or your life. This includes everyone from a religious authority, to a figure of authority, to the government.

The title of the novel is taken from the myth of Atlas, a Titan described in the novel as “the giant who holds the world on his shoulders”. A reference to the title appears in a conversation between d’Anconia and Rearden. During their conversation, d’Anconia asks Rearden what advice he would give Atlas upon seeing that “the greater [the Titan’s] effort, the heavier the world bore down on his shoulders”. Rearden is stumped by the question, and d’Anconia gives his own response: “To shrug”. Once you intellectually refuse another’s claim over your life and mind, you take ownership.

The economy of the US at the time of the novel is, just as many countries around the world, of the mixed variety. While some elements of freedom remain, these are largely side-lined in favor of the social good, and the prevailing view that the needs of others take precedence over your interests and desires. The unit of measuring what is ‘good’ is the group; the individual, and individualist actions, are the fount of evil.

Atlas Shrugged is probably Rand’s best work. It presents a unique, radically different take on human reason and morality, and challenges many conventions we hold without ever really questioning why we hold them. For all the critiques of the novel, from both philosophical and literary avenues, there is something in it with which people identify. If you read the novel and end up disagreeing with Rand, that is good – she believed that each person ought to reach their own conclusions, not just listen to, and accept, what someone else says.

If you haven’t read Atlas Shrugged, there’s an ongoing reading group on Facebook. They’ve read up to, and including, Chapter 6. Read those first 6 chapters and then join in the discussion.

The post Reflections on Ayn Rand’s ‘Atlas Shrugged’ appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
https://rationalstandard.com/reflections-ayn-rands-atlas-shrugged/feed/ 1 6680
Stand Up For Liberty https://rationalstandard.com/stand-up-for-liberty/ https://rationalstandard.com/stand-up-for-liberty/#respond Tue, 17 Oct 2017 12:34:55 +0000 https://rationalstandard.com/?p=6493 I believe a strong case can be made that liberalism has not taken hold in South Africa; indeed, our imperfect constitution is more liberal than most of the people of this country. That explains why an ANC rooted in communist/nationalist principles could enjoy so much support for so long. What can be done? I don’t […]

The post Stand Up For Liberty appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
I believe a strong case can be made that liberalism has not taken hold in South Africa; indeed, our imperfect constitution is more liberal than most of the people of this country. That explains why an ANC rooted in communist/nationalist principles could enjoy so much support for so long.

What can be done?

I don’t believe that your average South African is unwilling to accept the notion that each individual’s interests are best represented by that individual rather than a collective of some sort. We’ve gone from the equivalent of Middle Ages Europe in the pre-colonial era to colonialism, Afrikaans nationalism, and now African nationalism.

In other words, we have a tendency to romanticise our pre-colonial history because we didn’t document that history. At least the Europeans of the Middle Ages had writing. The oral tradition is highly malleable (the history that was written down is generally untrusted because it was usually written by white people and if you come into it being suspicious of all white people anyway, you see the problem), so when our forebears faced oppression for their race the oral history could be changed in order to facilitate a unified opposition to the oppression of that time.

I would bet good money that if you ask any ANC voter, they’ll tell you a version of history in which black people were living in a utopia before the arrival of white people. As I’ve often been told by my African nationalist friends, Shaka was a good king who used persuasion rather than force, who was playing a sort of game in which no one was seriously harmed and with no intention to violently dispossess other tribes of their property.

That sounds dumb, I know, but without any writing by people who suffered under Shaka listing why his empire building was wrong and how it destroyed lives through the Mfecane, as just one example, there’s nothing that has forced these people to consider the absurdities of their beliefs. The victims of Shaka are silent because it was both politically convenient and possible to ignore them.

Luckily for us, we now have a not-so-insubstantial body of African post-colonial history showing that things won’t be okay just because the person in charge has the same skin colour as you. What is needed now is people who won’t be afraid to challenge the dominant narrative that somehow outsiders can be blamed for the actions of the individuals we chose as leaders, and the supporting evidence for such an argument is being provided through the increasing liberalisation of parts of the continent. We can point to Botswana, for example, when Jacob Zuma blames the CIA for the downgrade of government’s debt.

It’s still not easy and it will require bravery to face up to the African nationalist establishment which has somehow managed to portray itself as a victim continuously since independence. I don’t know that politicians can be much help in this regard – even liberal ones, because, from what I’ve seen, their first instinct is to follow the crowd rather than stand up to it (I’m looking at you, DA – somehow BEE became liberal between Leon’s and Zille’s tenures as leader of the party).

What is really required is people willing to stand up for what they know to be right, backed up by evidence, and more importantly, a sense of right and wrong. People willing to go into their communities (luckily, South Africans tend to be social people) and stand up for the individual. I can make no guarantees that we will ever achieve true freedom here but I know for a fact that if we all stand on the sidelines waiting for someone to do the work for us, the battle is already lost.

So, stand up for liberty, in your workplaces, your social circles and your schools. The information is out there, particularly, I’ve found FEE useful for getting ideas about the effects of government policy on economic liberties, the Mises Institute is my go-to for public domain digital material on classical liberalism and liberty, and the FMF is where you can get detailed discussions on issues of liberty in the SA context.

The post Stand Up For Liberty appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
https://rationalstandard.com/stand-up-for-liberty/feed/ 0 6493
The Failed Social Experiment https://rationalstandard.com/the-failed-social-experiment/ https://rationalstandard.com/the-failed-social-experiment/#respond Tue, 17 Oct 2017 10:00:03 +0000 https://rationalstandard.com/?p=6566 Government is the Holy Temple of Statism. Its statutes and decrees are the ever-editable Commandments of the social engineers who sit behind desks, protected by the impenetrable wall of government bureaucracy. It is with great pride and honour that these men and women fight over the right to be able to design society as they […]

The post The Failed Social Experiment appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
Government is the Holy Temple of Statism. Its statutes and decrees are the ever-editable Commandments of the social engineers who sit behind desks, protected by the impenetrable wall of government bureaucracy. It is with great pride and honour that these men and women fight over the right to be able to design society as they please. It is also no mystery why this is the case. Power attracts the worst and corrupts the best; its psychoactive drug – which is that of control – incessantly hacks away at the little bit of humanity left at the upper echelons of the system.

What freedom means to people these days – the laymen’s version of it – is twisted to make room for unjust infringements on individual rights; rights we all benefit from, even you as you are reading this. Society must reconsider what it means to be truly free. We should revise all that we know about concepts such as human rights, and what it means to be an individual human being.

Human beings are extremely complex creatures driven by an almost infinite amount of forces. Being such complex creatures implies that we are all unique by default. It is what evolution and natural selection is all about. We all have a unique contribution to society, as we all have a unique set of skills that we can make use of. We are, by nature, endowed with the right to make use of our uniqueness. We have the right to be free in pursuit of our goals.

When we think of freedom, we tend to immediately jump to the part where we limit it.  It is what the modern welfare state is all about: how many rights and liberties can we forcefully take from people before it is considered slavery? We seem to be immensely apathetic to the fact that no one asked to be born into the society they were born into. The state is literally a central body of force that demands control over individuals from the day that they are born. To make matters even more ludicrous, people seem to simply not care about the fact that individuals are born within the jurisdiction of a certain collective by pure chance. That human being had no say to whom he or she wants to be bound to. That person did not consent to whichever government they’re “born to”. Period.

Now, I should point out at this stage that my abovementioned statement is usually countered with rebuttals such as “that’s life, get over it”. It’s a shallow argument that only serves as an attempt to refrain from debating the issue at hand: when are people going to get back their right to decide for themselves? It may be an inescapable truth that all humans are going to be born into a predefined collective, but the problem lies with what happens after they are born: why aren’t they allowed to disassociate from government at free will? They were never given a choice. What underlying natural right does a predefined body of power have to force association onto people? What happened to human beings’ natural rights?

When you have a right to something, you have claim to it. We can all claim to have the final say when it comes to whether we live or die; we have the inherent right to life. It is bestowed upon us not by arbitrary human authority, but by the laws of nature. It places nobody else under a positive obligation; that is, an obligation to do something. It merely imposes a negative obligation on other individuals: refrain from taking a human life and yours will be spared. It is the Golden Rule of ethics: treat others as you would want to be treated.

The same principles apply to two other rights we all share by nature as well: the right to be free to pursue our goals, and the right to own what we rightfully own. All of these rights place people under the obligation to refrain from infringing those rights. Human rights, by their very nature alone, do not depend on the actions of others to be fulfilled. It only depends on the absence of certain conduct on other people’s part. Your claims to your life, liberty and property merely demands reciprocal respect from those around you, the obvious exception being when you can only refrain from doing something by physically doing something  In such circumstances though, you are not obliged by any man-made law to act positively; the duty is imposed on you by the mere nature of the negative obligation. The logical question that any sane person will ask at this point is: when can these rights be limited? Also, on what authority does the limitation rest?

The inherent nature of a person’s natural rights automatically makes provision for limitations thereof: your rights do not entail the right to infringe on others’ rights. It is not by arbitrary man-made laws that you are obliged to refrain from harming others’ natural rights. You are obliged by the logical necessity of the situation. You do not have an automatic claim to someone else, their abilities and what they own, and neither does someone else have a claim to you, your abilities or what you own. It is the natural state of order between human beings.

That is what the state is supposed to represent: the natural state of order in society. The state’s only function should be to protect your individual rights. The state should not place duties on others to fulfil man-made “rights” authorised by government and government alone. Such so-called rights rest on no fundamental principle other than the rule of the majority. No person has the inherent claim to the services of another.

After considering all this, we should ask ourselves, is it really fair and just towards individuals if we force upon them obligations based on the odd coincidence that they happened to be born in a certain jurisdiction? People seem to conflate the concept of freedom from government with a society where anarchy reigns because there is no order. Involuntary government does not represent order. Voluntary government does. A free society is not a society with no central forces of power, but a society where collectives are formed, joined and left voluntarily. We as humans share the innate drive to band together, therefore there will always be some form of central power. The crucial distinction that we need to make is that such a body of power cannot arbitrarily impose authority on an innocent person.

Now, emphasis should be put on arbitrary authority. It is not arbitrary for a collective to impose force on a person when they are doing so to protect members of the collectives’ natural rights from being infringed. In such an instance, force is demanded to protect innocent people’s rights. It is, however, arbitrary to impose government force on an individual in order to fulfill another person’s man-made rights. It destroys the principle of rights only demanding negative obligations. Unfortunately, such an argument is usually countered with “but without government, a person wouldn’t have achieved what they did so therefore they owe society a part of their freedom”. Since when is it morally justifiable to deem a person as liable and in debt to a party who “helped” him or her, if he or she was forced to accept the help in the first place? A person can’t even leave the country and revoke their citizenship as they please, because they apparently owe government their lives.

No single human being on earth has the power to create new rights and infringe on the natural rights of others. It is irrelevant what the desired ends are. Individuals are never to be treated as a mere means to an end that is defined by the majority. Social welfare is not a justifiable reason to place an obligation upon another person to pay for it. It is terrible that we live in a world where there are people living in dire poverty and despair, which is why we need to encourage ourselves and others to be more philanthropic towards our fellow human beings. It is not, however, philanthropic to extort money from another person via government force merely because you want to help others and merely because the person you’re stealing from may be stolen from, because they form part of your collective by mere chance and no will of their own. Government authority that rests merely on the voice of the majority is asinine. A collective that isn’t based on voluntarism is a prison.

Have we as a society really sunk to the level where we deem a person’s freedom as being expungable so as to serve an apparent collective good defined by those in power? Is it really just to deem a person as a simple cog in the bigger machine, when the only purpose of that machine is supposed to be to protect all individuals to the fullest extent possible? Who are we to change that extent’s boundaries to our mere will? I leave you with the following quote:

“If the natural tendencies of mankind are so bad that it is not safe to permit people to be free, how is it that the tendencies of these organisers are always good.  Do not the legislators and their appointed agents also belong to the human race?  Or do they believe that they themselves are made of a finer clay than the rest of mankind?” – Frederic Bastiat

The post The Failed Social Experiment appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
https://rationalstandard.com/the-failed-social-experiment/feed/ 0 6566
The Nature of Government and the Fatal Flaw in South Africa’s Constitution https://rationalstandard.com/nature-government-flaw-south-africa-constitution/ https://rationalstandard.com/nature-government-flaw-south-africa-constitution/#comments Wed, 04 Oct 2017 22:01:33 +0000 https://rationalstandard.com/?p=6515 What needs to happen before South Africans realize that the institution of government is not a friend, a servant, or a protector, but a rival that only does good insofar as it is restrained? Our continued trust in government enables its continued expansion and its tendency toward corruption. The Problem My recent article on the […]

The post The Nature of Government and the Fatal Flaw in South Africa’s Constitution appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
What needs to happen before South Africans realize that the institution of government is not a friend, a servant, or a protector, but a rival that only does good insofar as it is restrained? Our continued trust in government enables its continued expansion and its tendency toward corruption.

The Problem

My recent article on the Western Cape provincial government’s decision to implement an authoritarian alcohol policy sparked quite a bit of controversy which I expected, and preempted in the article itself. Despite South Africans’ daily lived experience telling – shouting at – them that government only undermines them, the institution still enjoys widespread trust, not only in the Western Cape under the Democratic Alliance (DA), but nationally.

This is a particularly grave problem in South Africa due to what I consider to be a fundamental error in our constitution. But, moreover, it is a problem because those who trust government are invariably unaware of the nature of government.

On 24 April 2016, the former liberal and former DA leader Tony Leon wrote a valuable opinion piece in the Sunday Times, titled “Nkandla excesses exposes the glaring gap in founding law”. This article came only weeks after President Jacob Zuma confidently told African National Congress (ANC) supporters that the Rule of Law can be changed with a majority in Parliament. Those who who are a little more legally aware would know that the Rule of Law is not a rule of the law, but a doctrine which, as Judge Tholakele Madala and legal scholar Professor Friedrich von Hayek both said, permeates all law.

(The subeditor who chose Leon’s article title was incorrect in describing the Constitution as our “founding law”, as there has been complete legal continuity in South African constitutional law since 1910. The founding law of South Africa as we know it is the South Africa Act of 1909, passed by the Parliament of the United Kingdom. The Constitution is, instead, our supreme law.)

The article summarizes South Africa’s problem: We enacted a constitution for a moral saint – thought to be Nelson Mandela – and not for a real human being. As libertarians in South Africa and abroad had been warning for decades (centuries, if one counts early classical liberal thinkers), the nature of government means that those who are inevitably attracted to government are people who seek power. This is an absolute rule. There is no reality in which the institution of government does not attract this type of human being. This problem cannot be eliminated. It can, however, be tempered and suppressed, and for that to happen, certain institutions need to be entrenched in political society.

Indeed, if is often said – but rarely heeded – that when a constitution is being drawn up, the drafters must imagine that their very worst political enemy will be in government under the framework they devise. As Leon Louw has said in the past, at constitutional negotiations (like the one that brought Apartheid to an end) the party which will govern after the Constitution is adopted should be chosen at random (say, by a draw). On that basis, the drafting of the Constitution should commence. Thus, between the National Party and the ANC, each of the parties should have participated in the constitutional drafting on the assumption that it is the other which will govern. In this way, the best constitution would have been made: One which limits and decentralizes government.

It must be emphasized that when contemplating a political solution to a problem or devising a new political framework, the answer will always lie with institutions, and never with individuals – not “uniter” Nelson Mandela, not “outsider” Donald Trump, not “capitalist crusader” Herman Mashaba. These institutions must be both customary and legal, meaning that not only should there be strong legal restraints on government, but it must become unthinkable for those in government to do certain things.

The Nature of a Constitution

One of these (legal) institutions is a constitution.

A constitution, properly understood, is a special type of law that, unlike other laws, addresses itself to the government (not the people) of a society, and lays out what that government may, and crucially, what it may not do. The core message of constitutionalism is everything which is not allowed is forbidden. Constitutions are one of those things a society cannot afford to get wrong, because they are not transient, and it should always be assumed that governments will try to interpret them in a manner that benefits them.

The Constitution of South Africa, unfortunately, reads like a constitution meant to be transient. The Preamble and the Bill of Rights are filled with references to Apartheid, which will render it an awkward read for someone in the year 2117. This fundamental error undermines the constitutional (rigid, fixed) nature of a constitution by, essentially, giving South Africa a weird temporal status: We will always be stuck just after Apartheid. Time stands still legally.

In the Preamble we “recognise the injustices of our past” and set out to “heal the divisions of the past”. In the property rights provision, government is empowered to secure tenure which has been rendered “insecure as a result of past racially discriminatory laws”, and people who were dispossessed “after 19 June 1913 as a result of past racially discriminatory laws” may seek restitution or other redress for such dispossession. (As an ardent proponent of restitution, I believe this could have been framed far more appropriately, without using words like “past” or specific dates. Besides, the rei vindicatio action exists in our law anyway, allowing true owners to get possession of their property back.) Similarly, government is empowered to take measures to realize the right to education “taking into account the need to redress the results of past racially discriminatory laws”.

Examples like this abound.

The United States’ Declaration of Independence was a transient document, filled with references to the oppression of the British Empire. It was not a constitution, but a legal instrument which served one purpose and did so within a short space of time. Decisive executive action was naturally required for the Twelve Colonies to separate from the Empire. The war was fought and won. The U.S. Constitution was not meant as “a contract or a statute”, writes Professor Stephen Macedo in The New Right v. The Constitution, “but a majestic charter for government, intended to govern for ages to come and to apply to both unforeseen and unforeseeable circumstances.”

South Africa’s constitution, also presumably meant for the ages, has bound us up (theoretically) in perpetuity with the legacy of Apartheid and the requisite decisive executive action that goes with solving it. Our war against the legacy of Apartheid was made legally permanent and with it, an excessively powerful executive government was made similarly legally permanent. As a consequence, South Africa’s courts have time and time again reaffirmed the principle that because of the legacy of Apartheid, government must have extraordinary powers to deal with it. While the judges themselves might not realize it, this has directly enabled the kind of corruption we see today.

The Rule of Law

Another important legal institution that needs to be entrenched in any society that seeks to be free, is the Rule of Law.

To simplify, the Rule of Law means that society is governed by proper law, and not by the whims of man. The whims of man often take the form of law, but lack the legitimate character of law. (Indeed, do not confuse rule by law with the Rule of Law.) Proper law are rules informed by reason, evidence, and the time-tested principles of law, like rigidity, predictability, certainty, and proportionality. Libertarians would add to this and say that proper law are those rules which have a basis in the social contract: That government exists only to protect people and their property, and that in return people have sacrificed their natural ability to be violent in pursuit of their goals.

The Rule of Law is formally entrenched in South African law per section 1(c) of the Constitution, which states that South Africa is founded on the supremacy of the Constitution and the Rule of Law. But while the supremacy of the Constitution has seen relatively broad recognition, the co-equal supremacy of the Rule of Law has been afforded lip-service. From Herman Mashaba dropping “the rule of law must be upheld!” in every new Facebook post to Jacob Zuma ostensibly calling for the Rule of Law to be respected (but thinking it can somehow be ‘changed’ in Parliament), everyone knows about the Rule of Law, but very few people think of it as something consequential.

Research done by the Free Market Foundation appears to indicate that virtually all legislation passed by Parliament violates at least one tenet of the Rule of Law. For instance, essentially all laws which empower executive officials to make decisions, like create regulations or ‘determinations’, does so without any guiding criteria (save perhaps for the cop-out “public interest” criterion), meaning that it is the whim of man rather than the Rule of Law which governs in that particular respect. From mining licenses, to private school licenses, to healthcare regulations, officials have all the discretion in the world, and, in effect, create law which we must abide by. This latter function is supposed to be the domain of Parliament, not officials.

This, obviously, enables corruption.

If a regulator has the power to revoke or not renew a license without having to adhere to any strict criteria, it follows that companies will not want to sour their relationship with the regulator. It follows that bribes become a very likely occurrence. Arbitrariness and corruption are two sides of the same coin.

The courts, too, have tended to ignore the Rule of Law under the guise of ‘deference’. They endorse a minimalist notion of the Rule of Law whereby Parliament or the executive must simply act in accordance with the provisions of existing legislation, regardless of whether the legislation itself violates the Rule of Law. Where the courts have admitted that legislation violates the Rule of Law, like the Currency and Exchanges Act, they have refused to declare them unconstitutional, because, for some reason or another, the courts are unwilling to put two and two together, and understand that the Constitution provides for the co-equal supremacy of both the Constitution and the Rule of Law. It must, thus, follow that anything inconsistent with the Rule of Law is unlawful.

In South Africa, the apparent mixture of transience and permanence in our constitution, coupled with the fact that the Rule of Law has not been respected for centuries, has an oppressive and corrupt government as a consequence.

Jacob Zuma has simply reaped the rewards of an errant system of government. He did not create it. He sought power, which was handed to him on the silver platter known as South African constitutional jurisprudence.

Be Conscious of the Nature of Government

This situation is, however, not hopeless.

We must be careful not to think that ridding ourselves of Zuma is the key to return to liberal constitutional democracy; it is not.

Instead, the first step to moving in the direction of accountable and constrained governance is consciousness.

All it takes to turn the tide, is for South Africans to realize the true nature of government. Everything else will fall into place as a natural consequence of that realization, and nobody will be worse for wear. It is not a zero-sum game. This realization comes at the expense of nothing and nobody, save perhaps for corrupt politicians and their cronies.

Force, compulsion, coercion, and violence are the essence of government. These characteristics are inseparable from that institution, and rightly so – government, as a concept, came about because of the need for a forceful institution to protect individual rights. But just like one does not appoint a mercenary to run a nursery for babies, one should not appoint government to do anything other than protect persons and property from violence or fraud. This is what government is supposed to be limited to, and why force is a crucial ingredient to its nature. But government has not been kept to its proper role, and we have been reaping the fruit of this grave mistake for centuries. This is why acknowledging and appreciating the nature of the institution of government is key to solving all the problems which have resulted from this mistake.

When, or if, South Africans start this process of acknowledgment and appreciation, things like the Western Cape alcohol policy will become impossible. The Western Cape government would not be able to pass such a policy if it did not have broad appeal, which it clearly and ignorantly does have. Similarly, the entire notion of tenderpreneurship would immediately fall away. The over-reliance on government education and healthcare will end at once as communities, now disgusted by the very idea of government involvement in those things as a means of social control, band together and establish community-run private schools and clinics.

Legal and political scholars have been trying to evade the nature of government for centuries. They often acknowledge the general principle that government is a violent institution which must be constrained to only its social contract duty to protect person and property, “but”, they say, this or that circumstance necessitates a greater role for government.

In South Africa today, the “but” is the legacy of Apartheid. During Apartheid, the “but” was the possibility of black domination over the white minority. During the prior century, the “but” was the proximity between the British and the Boers. During the early Cape settlement, the “but” was the isolated location of the colony. There is always a “but” which has the effect of defeating the general principle.

It is, and has always been, high time to stop with the “but”. The “but” has only ever created more problems and more cause for more even more “buts”. This will continue unless people draw a line in the sand. This might sometimes mean forgoing the possibility of revenge or advancing certain group interests, but it is absolutely necessary to kick-start a free and prosperous society.

Conclusion

For as long as South Africans continue to envision the solution to our problems to be found in government, will we continue down this endless cycle.

This applies not only to the Democratic Alliance as well, but especially to the Democratic Alliance, because the DA now finds itself in many people’s political blindspots. One never truly appreciates the nature of government if particular organizations or individuals are caught in their blindspots. Nobody is exempt from the nature of government as a forceful institution which can inherently overpower any non-governmental actor for any reason. Whether it is me, Herman Mashaba, Pravin Gordhan, Donald Trump, Barack Obama, or Jacob Zuma in charge of government, the nature of government never changes.

Trust in yourselves, first and foremost, and in your families and communities. Never trust government, especially if it says it seeks to help, and especially if it is ‘your guy’ who is in power.

The post The Nature of Government and the Fatal Flaw in South Africa’s Constitution appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
https://rationalstandard.com/nature-government-flaw-south-africa-constitution/feed/ 2 6515
KPMG and the Loss of Ethics https://rationalstandard.com/kpmg-loss-ethics/ https://rationalstandard.com/kpmg-loss-ethics/#respond Mon, 18 Sep 2017 22:01:46 +0000 https://rationalstandard.com/?p=6446 Written by: Chris Hattingh Now that KPMG have ‘come clean’ on their murky dealings with the Gupta family, will we experience a resurgence in ethical conduct and the elimination of all corruption? Or will the status quo remain? I tend towards the latter, as it is extremely difficult to pin down a standard of ethics […]

The post KPMG and the Loss of Ethics appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
Written by: Chris Hattingh

Now that KPMG have ‘come clean’ on their murky dealings with the Gupta family, will we experience a resurgence in ethical conduct and the elimination of all corruption? Or will the status quo remain?

I tend towards the latter, as it is extremely difficult to pin down a standard of ethics in South African business, and South African society at large, by which we can adequately assess actions as ‘ethical’ or ‘unethical’. If anything, we are taught that the ‘good of society’ must serve as our standard. If this amorphous concept remains in place, we may well look back on the actions by KPMG as simply the tip of the iceberg.

Why should we act ethically, and by what standard?

I’m afraid that our understanding of ethics in general is insufficient, and when it is applied, it is done in the form of ticking boxes, instead of an integrated understanding.

KMPG’s report on the so-called ‘rogue unit’ in the South African Revenue Service resulted in the ousting of former finance minister Pravin Gordhan. While former KPMG CEO Trevor Hoole, COO Steven Louw, chairperson Ahmed Jaffer and five other senior executives have resigned, the auditing firm has not admitted to any wrongdoing. It merely “did not identify any evidence of illegal behaviour or corruption by KPMG partners or staff”, and admitted that the work “fell considerably short of KPMG’s standards”.

See no evil, hear no evil, speak no evil.

It seems that KPMG’s standard of ethics is, if you aren’t caught doing something illegal, you are good to go.

On the ‘Ethics and Compliance’ page of their US website, KPMG states “we are proud of our commitment to ethics and integrity.” Furthermore,

KPMG – through its people, values, programs, and policies – has made it a priority to help ensure that we have an ethical culture where everyone embraces a sense of personal responsibility for doing the right thing in the right way.

While a model of corporate ethics talk, the statement is very light on concretes.

In their Code of Conduct, they name compliance with laws as important and the need for individuals to take responsibility for their own actions. While that may look good on paper, the why of ethical conduct is never answered.

During my master’s degree studies, we were presented with a wide range of ethical theories familiar to philosophy students – theories such as utilitarianism (the greatest good for the greatest number) and Kant’s Categorical Imperative (you must do x because it is your duty) were given the spotlight.

While there were some good readings, being ethical in business boiled down to the imperative that you ought to be ethical because unethical behaviour is illegal. For those who desired a more philosophical perspective, the case was presented that you ought to be ethical because it is good for society and, even better, for the environment. In other words, you are ethical when you act according to, or for, an external standard. The individual and what is good for him is not taught in ethics courses.

If the other is the standard of what is good, ethics remains a matter of one feeling replacing another – there will always be someone or something else to which we must cede our own interests.

University students are taught that there cannot be an objective ethical standard, that all views are equal – what do we expect will happen when these students become business leaders? There is zero talk about long-term, rational self-interest in ethics. If we do not act for others or society or the environment, we must be selfish and therefore evil – this false dichotomy is hammered into students and they cannot hold an alternative in their minds, it must be one or the other.

Ayn Rand, however, developed an ethics which held reason as its method, and man’s happiness as its standard. As opposed to acting on the whim of the moment, or the vague concept of what is good for ‘society,’ Rand based Objectivist ethics on the individual. To act ethically is to rationally examine the world, to evaluate your values and how best to attain them. Those formerly in charge of KPMG did not act selfishly – they have now lost their jobs, their reputation and their standing. To act selfishly is to act with full knowledge of the consequences of your actions, not to try and cheat reality.

A proper code of morality, or of ethics, incorporates choice. When you act ‘ethically’ because the threat of force is levelled against you, your choice is removed from the equation and we can no longer talk about responsibility. To act out of duty removes your voluntary choice and negates your ability to decide for yourself whether path x or y is warranted. When we make ethics the realm of the legal, we remove the possibility of substantive engagement with the concept of ethics. Why is the individual the only legitimate base for a code of ethics? Because each person must decide for himself how he wants to live – we can only talk about morality when people are free to voluntarily decide for themselves how they want to live. Holding a non-entity such as society as the standard for ethical actions is a pointless exercise.

KPMG and others will be punished for their illegal behaviour. But we do not hold, never mind even acknowledge, that there is an objective standard of morality. We cannot, then, be outraged when these dealings come to light – we have no standard by which to measure them. The famous King ethics reports are held up, and taught as the ultimate guide for ethics in business, yet for all their talk about this or that part of King IV, the fundamental philosophy is flawed and ultimately self-defeating. We will only see a real uptake in ethical behaviour if people learn why they ought to be ethical.

Author: Chris Hattingh is a passionate advocate for free markets and free minds. He is a student of Objectivism and is currently a researcher at the Free Market Foundation.

The post KPMG and the Loss of Ethics appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
https://rationalstandard.com/kpmg-loss-ethics/feed/ 0 6446
Competition in the Market: All Sides Are Usually Winners https://rationalstandard.com/competition-market-all-sides-winners/ https://rationalstandard.com/competition-market-all-sides-winners/#comments Fri, 15 Sep 2017 22:00:00 +0000 https://rationalstandard.com/?p=6281 Two Kinds of Competition The word ‘competition’ is used to describe two different things, and while they are not unconnected they are so dissimilar that confusion between them leads to very serious misunderstanding. What makes matters worse is that the form of competition which is most prominent in the consciousness of the average person is […]

The post Competition in the Market: All Sides Are Usually Winners appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
Two Kinds of Competition

The word ‘competition’ is used to describe two different things, and while they are not unconnected they are so dissimilar that confusion between them leads to very serious misunderstanding. What makes matters worse is that the form of competition which is most prominent in the consciousness of the average person is not the form which is most important in the real world.

The word competition comes from two Latin words meaning ‘seeking together’, and refers to the situation when a number of people are trying to gain possession of the same thing, or of similar things. What it does not specify is whether there is only one thing so that of all those who are trying to gain it only one can succeed, or whether there are many so that many or even all of those seeking may gain them, but probably not to the same extent. These are the two kinds of competition.

First Type: Winners and Losers

When people talk about ‘holding a competition’ they are normally thinking of an arrangement where there will be one (or a few prizes), for which people will compete. There will be a winner, or a few winners, and the rest will be losers. Competitive sport, which plays a large role in the lives of most people as spectators and followers if not as participants, is always organised on this basis. Games are always about winning or losing, and in addition to the fact that each individual game has a winner and a loser (such games as races, many losers), there are often further elaborate arrangements to produce an ‘overall winner’ or champion – leagues in football and similar games, championships in boxing and golf.

It is worth noting in passing that the arrangements of the leagues and championships is highly artificial. There are in no sense genuine attempts to find out who is best (which is probably a meaningless concept anyway). Their purpose is to produce a winner or a champion and they have to produce one, even if, eventually they have to spin a coin to do so. The point is well illustrated by the refusal of some football leagues to accept drawn matches. Instead, a drawn match is ‘decided’ by a series of increasingly arbitrary procedures, like set shooting at goal.

From the fact that all games have winners it is a small step to believing that the purpose of playing games is to win them. This is dubious. The purpose of most competitions was originally to encourage people to participate in an activity which would benefit them in some way. The Ancient Greeks regarded athletics as a vital part of military training. Its purpose was to strengthen all the participants, not just the winners, and the competitions and the prizes were simply a means to induce people to take part and to do their best.

The idea that games were played for their own sake and not to win was strongly held in some quarters until quite recently, but the thing which has destroyed it is the overwhelming predominance of spectator sports played by professionals. The spectators want their team to win. For them (and they are the huge majority) winning is everything and the professional players have no option but to go along with this attitude. They are paid extra if they win. In games like golf and tennis the prizes for champions are enormous. They are professionals and they are actually playing for money, but the rewards are structured so that they are playing to win.

From this came two ideas which are almost universally held today: ‘Competition is about winning’ and ‘Where there is competition there are winners and losers’. In fact this is only true of the one kind of competition, hardly at all of the other.

Most of the ‘games’ kind of competition is artificial. Special rules are carefully crafted to throw up an unambiguous winner. In real life, outside of sport, there are few such situations. For one thing there are not unambiguous winners. The various pop-singers (or for that matter, concert pianists, or architects, or surgeons) in the world are in competition with each other, but who is the winner? If one asked a group of thoroughly knowledgeable people who is the greatest singer alive today, it is most unlikely that they would agree. There would be dozens of candidates, each with their supporters. And even if they did agree, another group would not agree with them. Real life situations do not throw up champions. Neither, of course, in any real sense, do games. A particular team wins the soccer league this year because the league is structured so that somebody has to win but somebody else will probably win next year.

Second Type: Everyone is Usually a Winner

The competition which is part of a capitalist economy and the competition which was identified by Darwin and his followers as forming part of the basis of evolution has very little in common with the games-type competition.

There are, indeed, some examples of competition which resemble the ‘games-type’ outside the sphere of games. One is the competitive examination when only a limited number of candidates will succeed irrespective of how well they all do. This is like a game with a limited number of prizes and, like a game, it is a situation which has been structured artificially. Another is competition for promotion in a hierarchical organisation. There are always fewer promotion posts than people who can be promoted, so that we have the case of many people competing for few ‘prizes’.

Particular situations can arise which look very much like a game or race. Several identified people are in line for a particular promotion; only one will get it; but even in these cases we are seldom looking at a simple case of winners and losers because those who lose in the one instance have other alternatives. It is not at all uncommon to hear someone say that the best thing that ever happened to him was to miss some promotion because it led him to change his direction in a way which turned out to be more to his advantage. It is only when people are locked into a hierarchy and cannot change their jobs, like in the Mediaeval church or a Communist Party, that such competition is truly internecine.

Such situations are in any case relatively rare. The type of ‘capitalist’ competition which takes place not only throughout human society but throughout animate nature, is something quite different. Let us take as our example a particularly obvious and well-known example of capitalist competition: a retailer operating in a reasonably free market. We can consider later whether his case is indeed typical. The first thing that we notice is that the shopkeeper does not spend his days confronting his competitors or indeed dealing with them in any way. He spends his days dealing with his customers, with his employees if he has any, and with his suppliers, that is to say, with people with whom he co-operates. What he actually does in order to compete is to try and improve the quality of his co-operation – essentially to serve his customers better.

His competitors are not a defined group, like an opposing football team. He may have a competitor next door, but he may not. He may be the only shop of his kind in his particular shopping centre but he is still in competition with others, all over the town and even beyond, possibly with others kinds of suppliers, like mail-order houses. Also, to a vague but real extent, he is in competition with people who sell quite different things. This is not a major factor in the life of a grocer, though it is not quite absent, but a seller of jewelry is likely to be very conscious that he is competing with the seller of sports cars and with the seller of overseas package-tours.

The Vastness and Decentralisation of Market Competition

The fact that ‘the competition’ is a vast and vague mix of different kinds of people, in different places and doing different things, many of whom the retailer does not know personally, and of some of whose existence he may be unaware, is a most important reason why competition seldom issues in overt hostility or conflict (though it can do, as we know from the taxi wars). In the vast majority of cases there can be no question of trying to destroy the competition and indeed of engaging in any kind of active conflict with them because they are too numerous and too largely unknown. In fact, our retailer seldom meets his competitors, and if he does it will not be for the purpose of competing but for the purpose of co-operating as in a chamber of commerce.

Normally, attempts to destroy competitors make no sense because more will simply arise in their place. Grocer’s shops do not buy out the competitor across the street because if they do somebody else will come in. The idea of destroying the competition can only arise in one of two situations. The one is where the number of competitors is artificially limited so that if a certain number are eliminated no more can come in. This was the situation created by the old Liquor Act in South Africa. In a certain area only a limited number of licences were allowed. If you could acquire all of them you eliminated all obvious competition . You had not in fact eliminated all competition. Liquor is in competition with non-alcoholic drinks and with other ways of spending money and people can go to distant places to buy liquor, but you have eliminated enough competition to give yourself a major benefit.

Role of the Law

The other situation where the elimination of competition makes sense is one of lawlessness, where a group of people hope to be able, by violence, both to drive out all existing competition and to prevent any new competition from arising. This policy was followed on a large scale by the European maritime powers in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries when first the Spanish and Portuguese and later also the Dutch and the British tried to establish monopolies of trade in particular areas and to keep out all competition by violence. The policy did not succeed and led to constant warfare, which in its turn led to the establishment of the rules which govern international trade today.

Among human beings for competition to be a peaceful process requires law but when law is present competition does not (as its critics allege) give rise to a society dominated by internecine conflict. People do not compete by trying to destroy each other; they compete by trying to serve their customers better.

The biological competition to which Darwin and his followers drew attention turns out to be very closely, analogous, not, oddly enough, to human conflict but to human competition under law. How this comes about is very interesting. The Victorians tended to see natural selection in terms of a sort of World Heavyweight Boxing Championship in which all animals fought each other to the death, until only the ‘fittest’ was left, but we now know that this is scarcely ever so. Animals very seldom fights members of their own species to the death. Territorial and mating conflict tends to take place either simply by posturing (as among birds) or by ritualised fighting in which little damage is done (as among horned animals).

Nature is ‘red in tooth and claw’ not in terms of competition but in terms of predation. Animals prey on other animals at a huge advantage so that the risk taken by the predator is negligible. Cats catch mice. (What can a mouse do to a cat?) Several lions together set on a buck, and usually a sick one at that. The difference between human beings and all other animals is that the humans can sometimes, by innovation in weapons, tactics or organisation, put themselves in a position to defeat others at a cost acceptable to themselves. Other animals cannot do this; they have to meet their own kind on a basis of equality, and a fight to the death on a basis of equality is a mug’s game, as was so well illustrated in the battle of the Somme.

So biological competition resembles human competition under law, with the principle that the better part of valour is discretion, universally followed by animals other than human beings fulfilling the role of the rule of law. There is constant conflict between predator and prey, but competitors seldom come into conflict, and indeed, just as in the human situation, often do not see each other or even know of each other’s existence. Snakes and cats both prey on mice and cats are more efficient predators than snakes. If cats arrive in an area where there has previously been only snakes, the snakes will find that there are fewer mice and their own numbers may decline, but they will probably never set eyes on the cats.

The Impact of Innovation and Change

Most of the time, in both the human and the animal situation, competition is essentially in equilibrium. Competition sets a minimum standard of efficiency which everybody has to meet, and everybody does meet it. It is in times of rapid change, and especially of adversity that competition becomes fierce and potentially internecine. It is important to remember that these situations are exceptional.

Spectacular innovation is a common occurrence in human affairs but very rare in nature because of the slowness of evolution. It can happen, though. When dogs were introduced into Australia (presumably by the first human inhabitants), their superior efficiency as predators led to the extinction of most of the indigenous Australian predators (but not, interestingly, of any of the prey species, which the dogs actually ate). In the same way the invention of the spinning jenny led to the extinction of the spinning wheel. There is a vital difference, however. It was the spinning wheel, not those who used it, that perished. A wolverine could not convert itself into a dog but a woman who earned her living by spinning on a wheel could, and many of them did become workers in a mechanised cotton mill. In wild nature innovation can indeed be catastrophic to some species but among human beings not. In human affairs it is processes, machinery or institutions that become extinct. People learn and adapt.

The other situation where competition becomes fierce and sometimes ugly, is where the external environment changes for the worse and a situation which was formerly in equilibrium is suddenly no longer. The market has contracted, the habitat has become smaller, the weather has changed for the worse, and there is less food than before.

There is a very important point to be noted here. Eugene Marais (the famous Afrikaans poet), in The Soul of the Ape, criticises the conventional view of the evolutionist of his time that the ‘struggle for survival’ is essentially a competitive struggle. The great enemy, as he points out, is inanimate nature, which will kill any living thing which is not able to cope with its challenges. The ‘unfit’ may be so – totally irrespective of any competition. If the climate becomes suddenly much colder some species and some individuals will not be able to survive. Those who were already suited to a colder climate and those that had the capacity to adapt, will survive – the others not. This is not a question of competition. Those who perished would have done so even if those who survived had not existed.

In the same way, by no means all failures in business can be attributed to competition. Many happen because the people concerned simply did not have all of what was required, lacking either material resources or skill or relying on innovations which failed or seeking to seize an opportunity which did not exist. Where successful innovation is highly desired and highly rewarded, unsuccessful attempts at innovation are bound to happen.

Government Intervention in Competition

Having noted all these things, we cannot deny that situations do arise where competition can become very ugly indeed, in situations of catastrophe, like an earthquake, a rare and therefore unforeseeable flood or drought, or a total war. In such situations it is normal for governments to attempt to suspend the process of competition, by such extraordinary means as rationing and price control as well as more indirect measures such as allowing manufacturers to form cartels in order to reduce the severity of competition among themselves.

Few would deny that in situations of true emergency some such measures may be justified but there can be little doubt that in the real world such measures have done far more harm than good because they have tended to be continued after the emergency has passed, and to be applied in situations which were not true catastrophes.

The essence of a catastrophe is that it could not reasonably have been foreseen, and that it will pass. If either of these conditions is not present, suspension of competition is entirely destructive. Where a misfortune was foreseeable, like a ‘normal’ drought or flood, it is most inexpedient that those who foresaw it and took precautions should be punished and those who did not should be rewarded, which is what happens if the impact of the misfortune is to be shared equally. If this is done, it will simply ensure that people do not exercise foresight. This was very much the effect of ‘drought relief measures’ in South African agriculture which led farmers to plant more and more maize in sub-marginal areas where there was little likelihood of getting enough rainfall. Similarly, to compensate people who build on land which is known to be subject to regular flooding is simply to encourage others to do likewise.

When the change is not a passing catastrophe but signals the beginning of a new state of affairs which is likely to continue for the foreseeable future, interference with competition is particularly undesirable. We have noted that the great advantage that human beings have over other animals in facing change is their superior ability to adapt, and the competitive process is a powerful incentive to adapt. Where adaptation is needed the last thing that should be done is to punish those who do adapt and reward those who do not. History, right up to the present, is littered with cases where the effect of government intervention has been to postpone a necessary and inevitable change and in consequence, to make the final adjustment both more drastic and more damaging than it needed to be, like attempting to dam a river and eventually causing a flood when the dam bursts.

Incentive Effect of Competition

The general point is that competition is the most powerful incentive to people to do things right, to be efficient, to render good service, and also to exercise foresight and to make necessary adaptations to changing circumstances. We can live with the suspension of competition for a short time though even then a price has to be paid, but in the long term the price exacted by any interference with competition is itself disastrous.

The incentive effect of competition is, of course, the one point that the two kinds of competition have in common. Competition certainly makes rugby players play harder and runners run faster. That, as we have noted, was what it was originally for. Today it is very far from clear what it is for. If winning is the only thing, what is the point of winning? Why play rugby or run marathons in order to win when you can just as well spin coins? In spite of everything that is said to the contrary, it is difficult to escape the idea that games really are played for their own sake and not to win, although people certainly do care about winning.

Conclusion

To conclude, let us sum up the differences between ‘games-type’ competition and ‘real world’ competition.

1. In games type competition the competitors are face to face, sometimes in actual conflict (as in boxing or rugby), always in direct contact. In real world competition one is only marginally aware of the competition. One is face to face with those with whom one co-operates.

2. Games are about competition and the purpose is to win. Business, or life in general, is not about competition and the purpose is not to win. Competition is part of the overall environment in which we pursue our actual goals – simply to live, to earn a living, to do a good job, perhaps to be famous as an outstanding practitioner of one’s art, but even that is not truly a competitive motive. Beethoven and Mozart were alive at the same time but were they in competition? Would either one be any less famous if the other had not lived?

3. In games those who do not win are losers. In competition there do not have to be losers. Some may fail irrespective of competition, some may fail as a result of competition but the great majority simply ‘hold their own’, meeting the standard that competition sets, being neither outstanding successes nor failures.

Finally we should notice that the idea dear to the sentimental Victorian socialists, like Galsworthy, that the poor are the ‘losers’ in capitalist competition, is hardly ever true. Typically in a developing society, the poor are newcomers who have come from a situation where they were even worse off (in Victorian England and contemporary South Africa, from the countryside to the towns, in modern America, from Mexico or Asia) in order to better themselves, making use of the opportunity which the prosperity of others creates for them. In the contemporary first world the poor are typically people who have been excluded by institutions the very purpose of which is to prevent them from competing (like minimum wages). So far from being the victims of competition, they are the victims of its absence.

Disclaimer: This essay was extracted from O’Dowd’s 1999 occasional paper, “Liberal Reflections”, for the Free Market Foundation. The essay’s name was changed from the original “The Two Kinds of Competition” and the headings were inserted by Rational Standard editors.

The post Competition in the Market: All Sides Are Usually Winners appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
https://rationalstandard.com/competition-market-all-sides-winners/feed/ 1 6281
Freedom of Movement and Communication is Crucial for Progress https://rationalstandard.com/freedom-movement-communication-crucial-progress/ https://rationalstandard.com/freedom-movement-communication-crucial-progress/#respond Wed, 13 Sep 2017 22:01:11 +0000 https://rationalstandard.com/?p=6252 Periods of Creativity Nobody who has even a slight acquaintance with world history can have failed to be struck by the occurrence of periods of extraordinary creativity in a few places and for quite short times, which have made greater contributions to human progress than the whole of the rest of the world put together. […]

The post Freedom of Movement and Communication is Crucial for Progress appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
Periods of Creativity

Nobody who has even a slight acquaintance with world history can have failed to be struck by the occurrence of periods of extraordinary creativity in a few places and for quite short times, which have made greater contributions to human progress than the whole of the rest of the world put together. It does not matter what aspect of human life you are studying; whether it is literature, or philosophy for fine art or science or technology. We find not only that there are such periods, but that the periods are the same. They are creative not only in one or two fields but in every field of human endeavour that existed at the time.

These periods of outstanding creativity are quite few. There is the classical period of China, the time of Confucius and Mencius, and the other Chinese Sages. At about the same time, there is classical Greece, the age of Aeschyius and Euripides, Plato, Socrates, Aristotle, Herodotus and Thucydides, Phidias and Praxiteles. The next period is less well known since most of its art and literature had perished and the only well known names associated with it are Archimedes and Euclid. It is the period of the kingdoms ruled by the successors of Alexander the Great, especially Egypt, centred on Alexandra, and Syria, centred on Antioch and forming part of the same world, the independent Greek cities of Sicily and Southern Italy, especially Syracuse. To appreciate the importance of this period we have to compare the level of general sophistication, both philosophical and technical, reflected in classical Latin literature with that of “golden age” Greek literature from four hundred years earlier.

We have to wait a long time for the next period which happened in the Middle East around 1000 AD in the Arab kingdoms, especially those centred on Baghdad and Cairo. Out of these came remarkable advances in science and mathematics and in architecture. The well-known Moorish architecture of Spain is an offshoot of this. After this, and in some ways directly derived from it, comes the flowering of Renaissance Italy, Michelangelo and Leonardo Da Vinci, Petrarch and Boccaccio, Machiavelli and Galileo.

After this we are approaching modern times in which creativity becomes both more widespread and more continuous, but we can still see a disproportionate amount in Holland in the seventeenth century, in Britain all the way from Shakespeare times to the end of the nineteenth century, and in the United States from the mid-nineteenth century to the present day.

We may also note that right through from the Middle Ages to present day Western Europe as a whole, while not equalling the special periods, was creative in a way in which the Roman Empire, the later Chinese Empires and the Byzantine Empire were not.

Correlation Between Freedom and Creativity

How are we to account for all this? From the sixteenth century onwards it is not difficult to detect the correlation between creativity and (relative) freedom. Though very far from free in the modern sense, the England of Shakespeare’s time, and the Republic of the Netherlands of the same period were not merely the freest countries in the world at the time, they were among the freest that there had ever been. As the seventeenth century went on Britain (now including Scotland) became freer, while the Netherlands, locked in a desperate fight for survival, first with Spain and then with France, became less so. The degree of creativity, especially in philosophy and science, moved accordingly.

Do we find a similar correlation in earlier times? At first sight, the answer to this question is no. None of the states involved in any of the earlier outbursts of creativity upheld individual freedom in principle; even for the members of the upper class. Republics were not necessarily better than monarchies in this respect. Socrates was put to death in the Republic of Athens (by popular vote) for teaching unacceptable ideas, and about sixteen hundred years later Dante driven out of the Republic of Florence and sentenced to death in absentia. But freedom does not have to be accepted in principle to exist in practice. It can exist because those charged with repression are half-hearted, or lazy or cannot agree among themselves. This was more or less the position in Elizabethan England.

Were the periods of unusual creativity also periods of unusual freedom, and if so, how did this come about? I think that the answer to the first question is “yes” and the answer to the second can be found. I gained the clue to this problem in a book describing the society of China under the Tang Dynasty that was one of the high points of Chinese civilisation around 1000 AD. The writer says that the people of the educated class at this time looked back to the time of Confucius as a golden age, forgetting that it was in fact a time of anarchy known as “The Period of the Warring States”, when China proper (that is excluding Tibet, Manchuria and Sechuan) was divided into five separate kingdoms, often at war with each other.

Now we see it, “The Period of the Warring States” would be a very fair description of fifth century Greece. If we started with the assumption that Greece ought to have been under a single government (as the later Chinese assumed about China), it could also be called a time of anarchy. Greece was divided into not five, but dozens of separate states which were often at war with each other. Renaissance Italy is the same story, with at least six major states, and some smaller ones, independent and sometimes at war. The Eastern Mediterranean after Alexander the Great was the same again. There were three major, and several minor, kingdoms all ruled by Macedonians, often at war with each other. The great period of the Arab world saw almost the very same kingdoms, now ruled by Arabs, independent and sometimes at war.

This is not to argue that what leads to creativity is warfare. The periods which we are considering were not exceptionally warlike, it is merely that in them people who might have been expected to be on the same side in war were sometimes fighting each other. There are plenty of examples of states devoted to war, and for a time very successful at it, which were not creative at all.

The great empires have often produced remarkable architecture and works of art, made possible by the accumulation of wealth brought about by conquest but they have never been noted for originality, least of all originality of thought. One can cite the Roman Empire after Augustus, China under the Tangs and the Mings, Spain in its period of greatness, and Byzantium over a thousand years.

Ease of Exit (and Entry)

The thing that the periods which we are considering had in common was not that there was a lot of war going on; indeed it is not clear that there was more war than at other times. It is that in each case, China, Greece, the Macedonian kingdoms, the Arab world, Italy, there were a number of independent states with the same language and the same culture, with the consequence that it was an easy matter for educated people (and others too) to move from one to another. When Socrates was sentenced to death in Athens, he could, if he so wished, and was probably expected to go into exile, which meant moving all of thirty miles to another city where they spoke the same language, had the same culture, and where he was known. When Dante was driven out of Florence, he went to live in Pisa and carried on with his writing. When Michelangelo quarrelled with the Pope in Rome, he went home to Florence and continued with his work. There are references in the Chinese classics to Sages moving from one kingdom to another because they disliked the policies of a particular king.

It is striking how many of these periods of creativity come to an end when “anarchy” was ended and unified government imposed. Particularly obvious, because familiar is the way in which the Roman world started to go downhill from the time of Augustus. The Han Empire in China (which succeeded the Warring State) was powerful and rich, but it was not creative like the time of Confucius and indeed was already looking back to that period as a golden age. The Renaissance in Italy went downhill from the time that Italy was brought under Austrian/Spanish control. The Arab world was destroyed by the Mongols but it did not recover under the unified Turkish Empire.

It is not difficult to see why this was so once we grasp that the precondition for creativity is freedom. When Dante was driven out of Florence he went to Pisa but when the poet Ovid incurred the displeasure of the Emperor Augustus, he was sent to live in the Crimea, just as under the Han or Tang emperors of China, Sages were sent to Hunan, and “dissidents” in both Tsarist and Soviet Russia were sent to Siberia.

By Galileo’s time, the whole of Italy was effectively controlled by Spain. If Galileo had wanted to leave Italy in search of greater freedom, the nearest place where he could have found refuge was Holland where the language, culture and religion were all different from his own. This was a far more formidable undertaking than going from Athens to Corinth or Florence to Pisa, but a lot better than going to the Crimea, Hunan or Siberia. People did move about Western Europe in search of religious or intellectual freedom helped by the use first of Latin and later of French as international languages, whereas in Roman or Chinese Empires there was simply nowhere to go. This no doubt explains the relative creativity of Western Europe as a whole.

We are looking at two things here, although they are closely linked. In the special cases which we have described, the ease of exit which the situation created gave to the people (or at least some of them) a degree of freedom which they could not otherwise have had. Beyond this, it inhibited the rulers’ oppressive impulses for the rulers did not wish to lose their subjects, and on the whole those who could most easily leave were those that they could least spare. Thus additional freedom was also enjoyed by people who did not wish to leave.

It is also possible that there was another factor at work. Because of the ease of movement and communication between these countries, they would have been exceptionally well informed about each other, which would have intensified competition between them and enabled them to learn from each other’s experience in a way which would have been prevented by the imposed uniformity of a large state.

Until the nineteenth century, ease of exit (which of course requires ease of entry somewhere else) does seem to have been the most effective source of freedom. The degree of freedom which is conferred, even in the best circumstances, fell far short of what we expect today and some parts of the population may not have benefited at all; but it was sufficient to make the places where it existed flower above all others in creativity and achievement.

Intellectual Freedom

It is interesting that when we look back in this way, it is intellectual freedom, freedom of ideas which appears to be most important, whereas in our own time we tend to be most impressed by economic freedom. This is a question of time scales. In order to flourish economically, a country needs economic freedom, and for a time it can do without full intellectual freedom, just as long, in fact, as it can base its economic progress on ideas and techniques borrowed from abroad, but in the long run, ideas are the most important. Countries, like Mainland China, that think they can have economic freedom without intellectual freedom will, in the long run, be proved wrong.

Fundamentally, Hegal was right and Marx wrong. Ideas come first as in fact Marx knew or why did he spend his life trying to develop ideas which he hoped would change the world? Even “means of production” are ideas before they are things. Newton’s laws of motion had to come before the Industrial Revolution, just as Einstein had to come before nuclear explosives and space travel.

Freedom is not a luxury that comes at a cost. It is the precondition of all human progress.

Disclaimer: This essay was extracted from O’Dowd’s 1999 occasional paper, “Liberal Reflections”, for the Free Market Foundation. The essay’s name was changed from the original “Freedom is the Precondition of Progress” and the headings were inserted by Rational Standard editors.

The post Freedom of Movement and Communication is Crucial for Progress appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
https://rationalstandard.com/freedom-movement-communication-crucial-progress/feed/ 0 6252
The tide of mass migration and the lonely tree of liberty https://rationalstandard.com/tide-mass-migration-lonely-tree-liberty/ https://rationalstandard.com/tide-mass-migration-lonely-tree-liberty/#respond Tue, 12 Sep 2017 22:01:07 +0000 https://rationalstandard.com/?p=6053 Roma communis nostra patria est Modestinus, D 50,1.33 Libertarian considerations are utterly necessary to analyze and grip the phenomena of mass migration. In October 2015 Martin van Staden gave us some splendid thoughts on this issue. This is a burning issue in politics, and remains unresolved and not intellectually grasped. More deliberation and engagement is necessary as […]

The post The tide of mass migration and the lonely tree of liberty appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
Roma communis nostra patria est

Modestinus, D 50,1.33

Libertarian considerations are utterly necessary to analyze and grip the phenomena of mass migration. In October 2015 Martin van Staden gave us some splendid thoughts on this issue.

This is a burning issue in politics, and remains unresolved and not intellectually grasped. More deliberation and engagement is necessary as confusion still reigns.

Van Staden explains the difference between true libertarians and people called by him “liberal nationalists”, people being against the mostly-Muslim mass migration into Europe.

I may be excused to give a short glimpse on myself first.

I am an immigrant to South Africa from Austria. I lawfully applied for a residence permit, received a temporary one, applied also for a permanent one, paid a deposit, received the permanent residence permit, but retained my Austrian citizenship. I enjoy a lot of fundamental rights here, save the political ones. I may not vote and may not be voted into a public office. That is perfectly fine with me.

Van Staden’s arguments

His arguments, some of which I follow and others not are in essence as follows:

– The state should only be concerned with public safety, maintaining the necessary military and police forces and maintain a judicial system to resolve disputes and violations of law. I do agree.

– Borders have only separating purposes, and stand in the way of individual rights. I disagree. Borders might be arbitrary and their purpose abused as we have seen with the communist “Iron Curtain” in Europe. But borders, fences, walls and limits also have a peace-preservation and -instituting function. The English word ‘town’ has the same linguistic root like the German word ‘Zaun‘ (fence). In German we speak of einhegen, einfrieden and that means ‘fencing in’. They are the physical embodiment of clear legal lines which we as individual persons use to mark the sphere of our rights. Maintaining those clear lines is an act of peace, a sign of pacification as every right has limits, including physical, geographical ones. Otherwise, it would be arbitrary.

– The essence of the challenge seems to be for him citizenship. I agree and defend this concept.

– National identity and cultural heritage is meaningless from an individualistic outlook. I disagree. I don’t mean to start a ‘querelle Allemande’ but certainly every individual has a right to cultivate his national and cultural identity and heritage, alone or together with others.

– A balanced view on Muslims is necessary. I agree and Van Staden rightfully indicates how many awful ideas, concepts and ideologies had been constructed by – mostly bearded (my emphasis) – grumpy old white men. He is especially right when he points out that the source of the problem is with us, and not with the migrants.

– He sees ‘democracy’, or better a very relativistic political system, as the open backdoor which actually creates the problem. I partly agree; the biggest creator of the problems is the welfare and nanny state.

– Van Staden maintains that a true libertarian has to oppose collectivism per se. I agree, but then he accuses ‘liberal nationalists’ of being collectivists. I doubt this is true, to advocate and defend a common national and cultural identity and heritage is certainly not collectivism. Also, assimilation is not a collectivist demand on immigrants but a clear and honest offer how to integrate yourself into a given society. The Free Market Foundation (FMF) does not accept socialist as members; that is not market collectivism but a clear message about the own substance and essence.

– Van Staden defines pragmatism as a philosophy without principle. Again I agree but have to emphasize that even with a strong and clear ideology you cannot escape being pragmatic in your day-to-day business. ‘Facilis summus in verbis’ as Otto von Bismarck once said. Dogmatism 24/7 is not helpful.

– Van Staden sees the (aporetic) collision and conflict between  the individual and the state. I partly agree, but I cannot consent with him denying the profound meaning of citizenship, nation and cultural heritage. He rightfully points out the hypocrisy of some reactions to terror and suppression. I share his commitment to “freedom for everyone, everywhere and always” but have to emphasize that freedom and a free market system has to be defended. How we can do that without damaging this principle and unintentionally enslave ourselves is one of the most challenging questions of these times.

And now some remarks of my own.

My thoughts

If we speak about terror and terrorist organizations we should be very clear.

The biggest terrorists since 1914 have been states waging totalitarian wars, falling into the hands of totalitarian ideologies, developing more and more threatening military systems of tremendous destructive capacity, and subduing the individual under more and more repressive rules. This all, of course, in the name of freedom, anti-terrorism, safety and so on.

“Nationalism” is defined by the Compact Oxford Dictionary as strong support for and pride in one’s own country – or nation – often to an extreme degree. For me, “fatherland’ and “mother-tongue”, my cultural and religious heritage, has a meaning and a purpose. I am defending it from being aggressively pushed out. Defending the own can never honestly be called ‘nationalism’, except by intellectually dishonest cultural Marxists. Individualism, fundamental rights, free markets and liberty rest on them, and are therefore under constant attack from nihilism, the result of  the Critical Theory that Van Staden rightfully mentions. Those have not the individual in mind but the empty creature, the empty sheet of paper, not a person in the proper philosophical sense but something with which the totalitarian helmsmen and his academic underlings can treat arbitrarily.

Does a right to immigrate exist either de lege lata (existing law) or de lege ferenda (the law as it should be in the future).

It is interesting that one of the first fundamental rights recognized was the ius emigrandi. It was formulated in the religious wars of the 16th century. As then, most people had been legally restricted to a certain territory (glebes adscripta since the late Roman Empire). It was a very important right given to people dissenting religiously from their rulers. It was also a liberal demand in the 19th century that taxes on emigration be abolished.

But does a right to immigrate into a certain country exist as a natural, fundamental right? Is any private person obliged to enter into any kind of agreement or contract with another one? The private autonomy, the liberty to enter into or not enter into any kind of exchange with others is a most important principle of a free society and economy. It is presently endangered by ‘anti-discrimination’ rules which make it, laughably, nearly criminal to discriminate.

Of course, we all discriminate for whatever purposes and this is an essential part of our freedom. It may be silly not to buy bread from a bakery whose owners have red hair, but it is not the concern of the state and the legal system to judge that. Imagine a life in which you have to justify, weekly, to some government official why you decided to take a particular job or why you have chosen that tailor or satisfied your drinking needs in this pub and not another.

With states as the organized political entity of a politically-organized community, it is the same. It must be the unrestricted political freedom of that community to say ‘yes’ or ’no’ to immigration, to open its doors or to keep them closed or to make  certain conditions and regulations for immigration. The fact that I am personally in favour or a generous immigration regime does not consume this political right of a certain political entity. To the contrary, a natural right to immigrate would destroy the substance and essence of this political entity as would the substance and essence of the FMF if it would be obliged to accept everyone as members regardless of whether those would be collectivists or all kind of socialists or communists.

The biggest blunder, is the welfare state. First, in any case and then in this specific historical situation. As the great German scientist Heisenberg discovered in the late twenties of the last century – quite a time ago but still not known by politicians – big masses of people act independently from the free will of its individuals according to the natural laws of science.

One of those laws is the second law of thermodynamics.

Basically, it proposes that nature tends to equalize all differences in potentiality. That means South Africans will not be surprised that poor people stream into wealthy areas, that areas of wealth attract poor people and that differences in population structures like age and low or high birth rates are triggers for migration movements. That does not mean that nothing can be done against unwanted migrations, as the Australian immigration policy shows, but the root of the movements must be clear. And Van Staden rightfully pointed out – with other arguments  – that the root of the problems lies with us, with European and North American structures.

A welfare state, a system which offers a basic minimum income and a lot of ‘free’ stuff, subsidies for this and that, attracts poor masses from pre-industrial societies. ‘Industry’ in the Latin sense means diligence, hard work. No pain, no gain. Our wealth is based on hard, organized and productive, economically-meaningful work, not on state interventions or public debt. But who can resist a painless income? If still today Angela Merkel refuses to set a upper limit on so-called ‘refugees’ and on the other hand presides over an extensive welfare state, organized with that specific German thoroughness, it is an offer to the whole world to come and cash in and then rest from travel in the hammock.

But with that the essence and the substance of a modern industrial state is destroyed. If you then add the fact that those people are in most cases cultural and religious aliens, you get a dangerous, poisonous brew.

In my humble opinion, the libertarian counter-example is Hong Kong.

You may freely travel into it, you receive a 3 month visa at the border after perhaps checking databases whether you are undesirable, and there are no further controls or no custom controls. You are then on your own. Absolutely no welfare state. You find work, open up a profitable shop or you perish. Nothing else. Therefore, you may find people Muslims there but – surprise, surprise – they are all eager to work

The question of Muslims building a Mosque is not like a competing barber shop as Van Staden points out and sees no problem as long as no force is initiated by Muslims. But that is the point. It is not about freedom to believe – that is so natural that everyone is always free to believe or not – but about the freedom to exercise a cult. And as long as Christians have in most Muslim states not only no right to exercise their cult, but are actively suppressed, there is no way that we can tolerate Mosques in our states and societies. As Karl Popper clearly pointed out, tolerance has its limits and cannot mean committing political suicide and subduing to totalitarianism.

Therefore, from a libertarian point of view, we have to distinguish between individual rights and aspirations, and behaviour and the political will.

As Karl Kraus remarked, if the Sun of culture is standing low, even dwarfs make long shadows. So it is a flood of stupidity here and stultitia there and in these floods are quite consequentially coming flood of barbarians or as the PC crowd likes to call them “poor suffering asylum seekers”. Stupid decadence invites a flood of barbarians, that is an old story. But the most amusing is to experience how the cognoscenti always explain that nothing can be done. There are always people – I call them ‘experts’ – who excel in explaining how you cannot do anything or something cannot work or why it is just themselves who cannot do anything. Maybe their minds have in childhood not been crippled by a classic education.

A contraire, a lot can be done! Following the Spanish legal scholar Alvaro d’Ors, mass immigration is an invasion, independently of the right to travel, to emigrate and to immigrate which in libertarian view may be given to an individual and that  economically makes sense. An individual freedom cannot be transferred to a group without the express consent of the state or the nation concerned. The mass transfer of men from their own territory into an alien one is an invasion, be they armed or not, or if they pretend to behave or not. Resistance against that is a natural right.

The ‘migrant’ being a member of a group of invaders is therefore a public foe. It has no relevance if he is personally peaceful or not. “Being nice” alone does not constitute a legal claim. In my interpretation he is a public foe regardless of being outside the own territory or within, being equipped with in most cases a dubious legal title or not, in the past recognized as this or that or not. In the same way public foes are those who as own citizens or organs of the state prevent defending or repelling such an invasion or in any other way assist it.

If you like to live in Rome, do as the Romans do!  And first of all wait for being invited!

The post The tide of mass migration and the lonely tree of liberty appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
https://rationalstandard.com/tide-mass-migration-lonely-tree-liberty/feed/ 0 6053
The Free Market and the ‘Survival of the Fittest’ https://rationalstandard.com/free-market-survival-fittest/ https://rationalstandard.com/free-market-survival-fittest/#comments Mon, 11 Sep 2017 21:55:00 +0000 https://rationalstandard.com/?p=6256 Biological Darwinism “Social Darwinism” was a doctrine that was popular in the last part of the nineteenth century. It started from a simplified version of the theory of evolution as propounded by Darwin (hence the name) and Wallace, namely that life is a competitive struggle for survival in which the fittest survive and the least […]

The post The Free Market and the ‘Survival of the Fittest’ appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
Biological Darwinism

“Social Darwinism” was a doctrine that was popular in the last part of the nineteenth century. It started from a simplified version of the theory of evolution as propounded by Darwin (hence the name) and Wallace, namely that life is a competitive struggle for survival in which the fittest survive and the least fit perish. As the ‘fit’ are superior to the ‘unfit’ and every generation is descended from the ‘fitter’ members of the previous generation, this leads to constant improvement and is indeed the mechanism of progress. The belief in automatic progress as a law of nature was older than Darwin, but Darwinism was considered to have explained how it worked. It was held that it was because life was a competitive struggle in which the fittest survived, that progress was automatic and inevitable.

‘Darwinism’ related to the process of biological evolution and the selection of biologically inherited characteristics. Social Darwinism moved away from this, and that is the main point, but before we get to that, it is worth noting that the simplified version of Darwinism set out above is not quite an accurate reflection of what Darwin said, and is very far from being how we understand evolution today. There are three points.

First of all the fossil record, as we now have it, simply does not reflect the steady progress postulated by Darwinism. Biological change seems to happen sporadically during particular eras when changes are, in terms of geological time, quite rapid, while for very long periods almost no change takes place. This has been called ‘punctuated equilibrium’. Normally, and for very long periods all, or nearly all species are in equilibrium and do not change much, but the record is ‘punctuated’ with occasional eras when very many changes happen quite rapidly.

These findings are not compatible with the idea that the engine of change is competitive struggle or the survival of the fittest, for that is a constant process and would produce the kind of steady change which Darwin himself believed in. It would appear that most of the time ‘the survival of the fittest’ is conservative in its effects, suppressing change, and that the changes are brought about by some extraneous force, most probably change of climate.

This brings us to the second point, one that was made nearly a hundred years ago by Eugene Marais, the Afrikaans poet who was also a remarkable naturalist. The struggle for survival is not only, and perhaps not mainly, competitive. It is also a struggle against a potentially hostile and always merciless inanimate environment. If the environment changes, some survive, some perish, depending not on any competition but on how capable they are of adapting to their new circumstances, in which those less fit before may suddenly be more fit now.

The last point brings us to the third issue – that we are not entitled automatically to call change progress. ‘Progress’ implies that things are getting better, which in its turn implies a norm of quality, and where does that come from? The fittest survive. Fittest for what? Fittest to survive. If the environment in which they had to survive was constant we would at least be able to postulate an ever-improving adaptation to the environment, but if the environment is subject to catastrophic changes, even that does not apply. From time to time a new ball game is initiated, and the process of adaptation has to start again.

Finally we have to note that if survival is our criterion of excellence (and what other criterion can there be if the whole process is driven simply by blind survival?), then the fossil record does not support the view that the latest is always the best. To take one recent finding which illustrates the point: A million years ago the most common species of buck in South Africa was the Impala. Since then more than twenty new species have evolved, more than ten of these have become extinct, and the commonest buck in South Africa is – the Impala!

The Problems of Social Darwinism

These are the problems of biological Darwinism. The problems of Social Darwinism are different. First of all one must be clear that Social Darwinism really did exist. For many years now nobody has upheld it and it has been used as a straw man for the purpose of attacking capitalism, which has been alleged by its enemies to embody Social Darwinism. However, in the nineteenth century there really were Social Darwinists, the most eminent in Britain was Herbert Spencer, who both preached the doctrine and praised capitalism as providing what the doctrine showed to be necessary. This is not the only time in history that capitalism has been gravely damaged by those who thought they were its friends.

The Social Darwinists contended that human society was also an arena for struggle for survival in which the fittest survived, or if it was not, it ought to be. This process, if left to itself, brought about improvement. Insofar as human society was organised to help the unfit to survive, this was wrong and should be stopped as it retarded progress and could, if taken far enough, lead to the deterioration of the human species. Moderate Social Darwinists contented themselves with grumbling that the poor reproduced themselves faster than the rich (which, in fact, seems to suggest that the poor were in fact ‘fitter’ than the rich, but few people took that point), but the extremists, including Herbert Spencer, denounced all forms of provision for the unfortunate whether public or private, socially harmful; according to Herbert Spencer the unsuccessful should die. If they did not die before they reproduced (which was first prize) their children should die too.

According to Spencer, capitalism was the ideal system, provided it was not spoilt by public provisions like the Poor Law (which he denounced) or private charity. It was competitive. The winners become wealthy, the losers become poor, the most complete losers become destitute, and if only silly people would not interfere, would die. This would bring about progress.

Literal-Minded Darwinists’ Preference: Warfare and Killing

We should note in passing that the Social Darwinists had problems with other more literal-minded Darwinists of whom the American novelist Jack London was an example. These people contended that capitalism was a horrible deviation from the proper struggle for survival, which was physical. In a ‘natural’ society constant warfare and killing would select fine, big, strong, physically healthy specimens (like Jack London) whereas capitalism, contrary to nature, brought to prominence weedy specimens like Rockefeller and JP Morgan.

This view is completely self-contradictory. If you want to rely on natural selection, then whatever is, is right. ‘Nature’ has deemed cockroaches, termites and oysters to be very fit indeed because they have survived, almost unchanged, for hundreds of millions of years, which is a great deal more than can be said for homo sapiens. If Rockefeller does better than Jack London, that is how it is. What he has is ‘fitter’ than what Jack London has. If, however, you want to impose your own rational or moral criteria of what is good (London is better than Rockefeller) then you can no longer invoke natural selection. You are asking for an ‘artificial’ society, which is what you are complaining about.

The fact is, of course, that since human beings are intelligent and foresighted there can be no ‘natural’ orders of human society, if by that we mean one in the formation of which human judgement and wishes have played no part. While no human society has ever been entirely constructed as a blue-print planned by a few people, all societies have evolved through the interaction of rational human beings with each other. This is human nature, so this is natural.

Where Herbert Spencer Gets it Right

Herbert Spencer’s position did not suffer from this weakness. He would have had no difficulty with the idea that he was talking about progress in strictly human terms; things getting better in the opinion of those most directly affected. Capitalism is a system where people compete to promote their own self-interest by serving the needs of others. Those who succeed are those who serve the needs of others most successfully, in the opinion of the people who are served. So, as the fittest prevail, the needs of all are served more and more successfully, more and more people get what they want, and that is progress.

So far this analysis is correct, except that the last statement is disputable. It runs into the criticism of those (quite numerous) people who believe that people should not have what they want; they should have what other people say is good for them. The trouble with capitalism, these people say, is that it does give people what they want, so it gives rise to phenomena like pop music and Elvis Presley whereas socialism creates real art, like piles of bricks in the Tate Gallery. There is no ultimate answer to this complaint except to ask, what is it that entitles some people to tell other people what is good for them, who the ‘some people’ are to be, and how are they to be selected? Nobody has ever answered these questions satisfactorily either.

So far, Herbert Spencer’s position is fine, but we now come to the two points on which it is not fine. Built into it are two assumptions which are false, and which render it completely invalid.

The Poor Aren’t ‘Losers’

The first assumption is that the poor, or even the destitute, in a capitalist society represent the losers in competition. This is false. First of all, as we have pointed out in another essay, capitalist competition does not strictly speaking, produce losers. Secondly, normally in a capitalist society the poorest people are in fact newcomers who have come from a worse environment in order to better themselves – in the process showing a considerable degree of ‘fitness’. The recent migrant into Greater Johannesburg from the Northern Province, into Cape Town from the Transkei, into the United States from Mexico, or, in Herbert Spencer’s Britain, into Glasgow from the Highlands of Scotland, is not a loser.

The Fallacy of Collectivist Determinism

The second point is far more fundamental. Darwinism is about the selection of inherited characteristics and for Social Darwinism to have any validity we have to believe that the differences in behaviour which make the difference between success and failure, as between individuals, as between groups, as between nations, depend to an important extent on inherited characteristics. Spencer would have believed this, as did a great many people in his time. It was the belief out of which ideas of racism flowed.

The idea is an old one and has been held by many people in many cultures. People, whether as nations or as parts of a nation, a ‘class’, who are doing particularly well at any time have often, perhaps always liked to assure themselves that their success will last by claiming that they owe it to a fundamental, inherited, biological superiority, so that they are as different from other people as lions are different from jackals, and therefore are sure to prevail. The ancient Greeks had such a belief about themselves, Aristotle saying that all non-Greeks were incapable of the ‘good life’. The ruling orders in the Middle Ages had such a belief about themselves, not as a nation but as a class. The Chinese had such a belief at various times in history, as had many British in the nineteenth century and many Germans in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries.

One can readily understand why people wanted to believe such things, but unfortunately for them, and very fortunately for humanity, they were wrong. History is full of the stories of people preening themselves on their inherited superiority to others, who later (not always much later) equalled or surpassed them; the ancient Greeks, conquered first by the “semi-barbarian” Macedonians, then by the wholly barbarian Romans; the Romans who were quite willing to acknowledge the civilisation of the Greeks and Egyptians, and even of the Babylonians and Persians, writing off the Germans (including the ancestors of the English) as irredeemable savages; the Chinese preening themselves on their superiority to both the Europeans and the Japanese; the Europeans sure of their superiority to the Japanese; Japanese and Chinese alike through the centuries, writing off the Koreans as hopelessly stupid and lazy. Perhaps the most remarkable of all was the Englishman in the nineteenth century who said that the United States could never amount to anything because it had been populated by “the defeated classes of the defeated nations of Europe”. The statement was perfectly true. It had been, but that fact did not prevent it from becoming the richest and most powerful country in the world, and also, for a considerable time, the world’s main source of both scientific and technological innovation.

The biological, or racist, interpretation of the source of progress and achievement in human affairs is not tenable. It is simply not supported by the facts. The other great set of facts which contradicts it is all the records of the massive difference in achievement of people of the same ethnic origin (and with the same cultural background) under different social systems; East and West Germany between 1945 and 1990, North and South Korea, the Irish in America and the Irish in Ireland, Indians in Britain (or in South Africa), and Indians in India, and so on and on.

Learning From Others

The only conclusion which is in accordance with the facts is that we are looking not at genetically inherited characteristics but at learnt behaviour, and that all people can learn. This is not to deny that there are big differences between individuals in their ability to invent and innovate, but there is no reason to suppose that such individuals are commoner in some populations than in others. What is true is that such individuals are encouraged and helped in some cultures and persecuted and kept down in others, so that we see invention and innovation flowering in Italy at one time, in Holland at another, then in Britain (especially Scotland), then in Germany, the United States, Japan, then Korea. Where next? But even if some nations did not produce many innovators, they could still learn from others. Germany, the United States and Japan each went through a period when their progress was based mainly on applying the discoveries of others. In fact, each in turn became great discoverers but if they had not they could still have progressed very far.

It is important to remember that even the most innovative and successful nations have learnt far more from other people than they invented for themselves. An American space shot depends on mathematics originated in ancient Babylon and developed in Greece, in the Arab world, in Italy, France, England and Germany. It depends on a system of numerals coming from India via Arabia, and an alphabet from the Lebanon. It could hardly happen without paper, invented in China, where also, explosives and rockets were invented.

Newton said, “If we have seen further than our predecessors it is because we stood on the shoulders of giants”. This is true of all innovators, even the greatest, whether in science, technology, the arts, or anywhere else. The innovator takes a huge mass of already existing knowledge and technique (including such things as mathematics) and makes quite a small addition which opens up a major new possibility.

It follows that the other great thing that is necessary for material progress, apart from a social system that allows, encourages and rewards initiative and innovation, is access to the mass of knowledge that has been generated in the rest of the world. Any nation, or small group of nations which was forced by isolation to invent everything for itself was bound to fall behind those who could draw on the whole world, and this fact is quite sufficient to account for the relative backwardness of Africa South of the Sahara in past history.

Choice

So Herbert Spencer’s Social Darwinism was just wrong. In biological evolution there is nothing that the losers can do. A zebra cannot decide that the answer to its problem is horns, or a bat that what it needs is feathers, but the Mediaeval Europeans could decide that the Arabic numerals (the ones that we use today) were better than their own (the old roman numerals, XII, etc) and adopt them. If they had not done so, modern mathematics and therefore modern science and therefore modern technology could never have developed in Europe. Peter the Great of Russia could and did decide that the way that the Dutch built ships was better than the way the Russians did, and arranged for the Russians to learn ship-building in Holland. The Japanese decided to copy all sorts of things from Europe and America, some of which they later improved on, and so on.

Progress does not require that the unfortunate and unsuccessful should perish. If we want a materialist (as distinct from a humanitarian) reason why the unfortunates should not be allowed to perish, we can find it in saying that everybody can still learn and so come to make a contribution. Capitalists in particular do not want anybody to perish since the more people there are that they can employ (and the healthier these people are) the better is it for them.

Institutions and Ideas Perish, Not People

However, Darwinism does have something to teach us about social and economic progress once we realise that the things that compete and are selected as fit or unfit by competition are not people (people adapt and learn) but institutions, systems and ideas. The socio-economic systems of both the Soviet Union and Yugoslavia were selected out and perished, just like apartheid. The same thing is happening on a small scale all the time and everywhere. Different systems and technologies compete; the better prevail and the less good are abandoned, companies succeed and companies fail, as do products. Competition, both on a large and on a small scale is constantly both providing the incentive for innovation and sorting out the successful innovation from the unsuccessful, providing in fact for the survival of the fittest, that is for those which meet our needs most effectively.

There is something here that we can learn from Spencer. He deplored intervention to prevent the unfit from perishing. He was wrong, not because he had mistaken the connection between competition, selection and progress, but because he had mistaken who and what it is that is competing. It is indeed wrong for governments to intervene, as they constantly do, to prevent the perishing not of ‘unsuccessful’ individuals but of unsuccessful companies, industries and activities. To prop up unsuccessful industries by means of tariff protection or subsidies or by suppressing competition (often the real purpose of nationalisation) is damaging to progress, and while it would be rash to say that these things can never be justified in any circumstances, the presumption is always strongly against them, and when they are done they must be clear and unambiguous temporary measures (nationalisation which in its nature is permanent can never be sensible) aimed at smoothing a process of change, never at preventing it.

Capitalist Consumerism

We must be clear that in the process which we are discussing we are not talking about ‘natural selection’ in the strict sense, that is selection by blind natural forces, which raises the serious question why whatever they produce should be regarded as progress. We are talking about selection by intelligent acting human beings. In capitalist competition people compete to serve the needs of customers, whether by supplying products or by supplying services. The customers decide which of the alternatives offered to them are ‘fit’ and which are not. Progress means that the wishes of people are met more satisfactorily than before, in the opinion of the people themselves.

The competition of social and political systems operates in the same way, though less efficiently because of the constant use of force and fraud to prevent free choice. Nevertheless the systems are ‘offered’ to people to serve their needs, and the people eventually decide whether they are fit or not. The history of the Soviet Union shows that even the most horrendous and sustained use of violence and deceit cannot prevent the process from prevailing eventually.

Don’t Reward Those Who Refuse to Adapt

There is a last point to be made. There is, as we have seen, no objection to caring for the unfortunate, but there is every objection to rewarding those who refuse to adapt. Not only progress but also survival in a world that is constantly changing depends above all on the willingness and ability to adapt. What we need for progress is that the innovators should be free to innovate; that they should have to compete to show that their innovation is worthwhile; that those whose innovations are chosen should reap a reward; and that the mass of people who are not innovators should follow, or imitate the successful innovators. If we want to prevent progress, all we have to do is to take away the reward of the innovators and ‘redistribute’ it to those who prefer not to adapt. Quite a lot of societies in the past have done this and have been fairly successful in preventing progress. Is that what we want to do?

Disclaimer: This essay was extracted from O’Dowd’s 1999 occasional paper, “Liberal Reflections”, for the Free Market Foundation. The essay’s name was changed from the original “The Fallacy of Social Darwinism” and the headings were inserted by Rational Standard editors.

The post The Free Market and the ‘Survival of the Fittest’ appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
https://rationalstandard.com/free-market-survival-fittest/feed/ 1 6256
Protecting Truth from Willful Ignorance and Deceit https://rationalstandard.com/protecting-truth-willful-ignorance-deceit/ https://rationalstandard.com/protecting-truth-willful-ignorance-deceit/#respond Fri, 08 Sep 2017 21:25:00 +0000 https://rationalstandard.com/?p=6240 Objective Reality He who controls the present controls the past, He who controls the past controls the future. George Orwell In spite of the general assumption in the essay, What is Truth?, that there is an external reality which does not yield to our wishes and is not affected by our beliefs, there is a […]

The post Protecting Truth from Willful Ignorance and Deceit appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
Objective Reality

He who controls the present controls the past,
He who controls the past controls the future.
George Orwell

In spite of the general assumption in the essay, What is Truth?, that there is an external reality which does not yield to our wishes and is not affected by our beliefs, there is a persistent undercurrent of belief or half-belief that if only everybody, without exception, agreed that something was so, then it would in fact be so. In a general form, this idea is absurd. For thousands of years, probably hundreds of thousands, every single human being believed that the Sun rotated round the Earth. Does that mean that it actually did? If so, when did it stop? When one person suggested that the Earth might go round the Sun? When one person became convinced that it did? When the majority of people believed that it did, or when everybody did so? When half the people believed one thing and half the other, what did the poor Sun do? It is no use saying, “There is my Sun and your Sun,” because we know perfectly well that there is only one Sun, that it is as it is, and that if I act on false beliefs about how it is, I will suffer the consequences.

Until we get involved in space travel the practical consequences of ‘how the Sun is’ are not important for most people, but there are other areas when the facts are very important indeed and where universal but wrong beliefs did not help at all. One of the most obvious is the cause and treatment of disease. For thousands of years it was believed that blood-letting was an effective cure for fever, and following the belief large numbers of people were treated and notwithstanding the belief, they died. Recently other methods of treatment were found and as a result people now live longer. If command or common belief could make truth, all diseases would have been treated successfully at all times and there would have been no increase in the expectation of life over the last hundred years.

There is, of course, one rather important area of reality that does not respond to human wishes and beliefs and that is human behaviour. If it is only human behaviour that we are concerned with, to create a universal belief may well be effective. The trouble is, however, that nearly all human behaviour involves interacting with non-human reality so that behaviour based on false beliefs quite simply does not work. The Black Death could not have been prevented by making everybody believe that the plague was prevented by eating garlic. At least this would have done no harm, but if it was believed, as in some places it was, that the way to combat plague was to kill off all the cats, the belief could do great harm, the more harm the more it was actually acted upon.

The issue is complicated by two things that exist extensively in human society. The one is arbitrary convention and the other is traditional myth.

Arbitrary Conventions

Arbitrary conventions are very common. They arise when it is desirable, or in some cases vitally necessary, that everybody should act according to the same rule, but it does not matter what the rule is as long as there is one. A perfect example is the rule of the road. There is absolutely no advantage in driving on the left side of the road rather than the right, nor vice versa, but it is literally life and death that everybody should drive on the same side. Hence there is no objective fact or state of affairs that has to be ascertained. All that is necessary is that everybody should agree.

Societies are full of arbitrary conventions, many of which are much more subtle in their purpose than the rule of the road. The purpose that they all serve, in many different ways, is to enable people to know in advance what behaviour they can expect and, more important, what behaviour they can be sure of not getting from other people. Beyond the rule of the road, there are subtle conventions in driving which differ from one town to another, giving rise to the near-universal perception that people from other places do not know how to drive. It is small differences in manners and conventions of behaviour between one society and another that give rise to the stress and anxiety associated with travelling in foreign countries, sometimes called ‘culture shock.’

Arbitrary conventions are extremely widespread and completely necessary, but properly speaking they should have nothing to do with this enquiry. The reason why they cause confusion is that it is quite common, and used to be much more so, to teach the arbitrary conventions of society to children as if they were cosmic truths and not to distinguish between rules based on social convention and rules based on prudential consideration of the facts of external reality. Is ‘wash your hands before eating’ a social convention or a prudential act to protect oneself against infection? In fact it is both, and so are a great many others.

Many conventions are not truly arbitrary. It is highly desirable, from the point of view of your personal health, always to wash your hands before eating. By making it a convention so that everybody expects everybody else to do it, it is made easier. Everybody accords to everybody else the reasonable space to do it. It is also made more difficult not to do it.

Traditional Myth

These kinds of conventions shade into the area of traditional myths. These played a very important role in earlier societies and exist in our own society much more than we often like to think. They consist in a convention that serves an important social purpose, supported by a story which is factually untrue, which give a sanction to the convention. So, for example, in a traditional society there is a taboo on cutting living wood, which serves the extremely important purpose of preventing the deforestation of the countryside. The taboo is sanctioned by a story that the spirits of the trees will avenge themselves on anyone who cuts living wood.

Much of what our immediate ancestors pleased to call ‘superstition’ was of this kind, and in order to understand it we have to accept two points that the modernist rationalists do not like. The first is that people have discovered by experience what works and what does not work without having a valid theoretic base for their knowledge. ‘Primitive’ people knew a great deal that was true without knowing why it was true. The other point is that over time natural selection sorted out ways of behaviour that worked better from those that worked worse, and it is the better ones that survive. Patterns of behaviour that have survived for a long time are certainly serving a purpose and while there may be better ways, we need to be sure we have identified these before we attack such patterns.

As long as things remain unchanged these myth-backed conventions serve useful purposes, but their drawback is that they stand in the way of change. When new discoveries or changed circumstances make it possible and desirable to change the convention, the myth stands in the way.

The very purpose of the myth is to make change in the convention impossible. (This may not be its only purpose but that is another story.) This is important since the conventions will always require behaviour which is in some way burdensome, usually involving the sacrifice of short-term to long-term interests, such things as not eating seed-corn or slaughtering draught animals or breeding stock or enforcing all the complex requirements around the proper care of the young.

The Rationalist Approach

Modernist reformers hated these myths because they stood in the way of change, denounced them as ‘irrational’, called them ‘superstitious’, and demanded that they be ‘swept away’. Reason was to take their place. All rules of behaviour were to be tested by conscious reason and only conventions which were justified by reason were to have any force.

This was all very well up to a point. As the world changed under the impact of new knowledge and new technology social behaviour did have to change (as it has done, vastly). ‘Superstition’ did sometimes stand in the way of changes that would definitely be beneficial, for example in preventing or curing disease.

However, the rationalist approach ran into no less than three problems. The first was that the rational reformers did not always know what they were doing. In general, they did not know as much as they thought they did. Typically, they would focus their attention on one aspect only of a convention of behaviour which was often much more complex than they had realised and served not one purpose but many. They were forever throwing out babies with bathwater, giving rise to the now familiar phenomenon of social reform producing new social evils.

The second problem was that reason is not as simple and cogent as rationalists liked to believe. The idea that was still being seriously put forward just a few years ago that if only everybody would embrace reason, everybody would agree on all essentials, is just not true. One of the main consequences of their replacement of ‘superstition’ with ‘reason’ has been the breakdown of social uniformity. The old conventions have not been replaced by a new rational one but by a multiplicity of new conventions or by none. Indeed the most striking difference between a ‘modern’ society and a ‘traditional’ one is the far larger areas in which individuals are free to make their own choices.

In many areas this change, whether or not it was intended by anybody, has been highly beneficial. As societies have become richer, with more resources, so having bigger margins against misfortune and disaster, it has become increasingly less necessary to insist on uniformity of behaviour and therefore possible to reap the advantage of not doing so. These consist not only, or even primarily in the lifting of the burden which compelled conformity placed on individuals; even more important is the scope which individual freedom creates for experimentation and the competition of different ways of doing things which is the main engine of progress in any society. Throughout history relatively free societies have always progressed more and faster than unfree ones.

Nevertheless, there is a price to be paid for this that accounts to a large extent for the widespread disillusionment with modernism that we see in the contemporary world. This links up with the third problem of rational reform of behaviour, namely that reason fails to give people adequate motives to defer immediate gratification for the sake of the long term, and to subordinate the interests of each individual to those of all other individuals, which is the proper way of regarding the concept of the individual versus society. Reason teaches each individual that by being sufficiently clever and unscrupulous, he or she can get away with behaviour that, if practiced by everybody, would be totally destructive. It is not for nothing that Shakespeare’s most extreme villains, Iago in Othello and Edmund in King Lear, are both rationalists.

Hence, very largely, came the discontent of modern society. Everybody, or at least too many people, were trying to live off ‘society’. “Live now, present a bill to ‘society’ later”. Governments, in trying to appear to meet these demands and not to present the bill for them, were loading burdens onto future generations or, quite simply, preparing future bankruptcy. The equivalent of seed corn was being consumed; the young were not being adequately cared for; and large numbers of people were damaging themselves through their unwillingness to take the long-term consequence of their behaviour into account.

This now brings us back to our starting point, for as we have become disillusioned with rationalism there has been a revival of the question: Is it possible to create myths as a way of influencing human behaviour? The idea is not a new one. Plato, in The Republic specifically recommends that rulers should create myths and that these should be based on false information. Plato, too, lived in a time and place when traditional conventions of behaviour were breaking down under the impact of change and reason, and when people were worried about some of the consequences of this breakdown.

In a situation where the inadequacy of reason is becoming evident people may revert to old beliefs – be they myths or not – as is happening in many parts of the world in the movements which are sometimes called ‘fundamentalist’, but it is very unlikely that they will buy new myths which do not appear to be rational, so that new myths, as Plato realised, will necessarily be based on disinformation.

Rewriting History, and Creating Truth

This brings us to the passage from George Orwell that is cited at the top of this essay. “Those who control the present control the past; those who control the past control the future.” Those who control the present – assuming that their control is total, can falsify any facts that they choose; they can rewrite history, they can suppress, distort or fake research data on any subject; they can make it appear that absolutely anything has been proved.

It is the hankering for this kind of power that underlies the constantly recurring nostalgia for the idea that we can make the truth if we can only persuade everybody to believe, or pretend to believe that it is so. This is not only the resort of tyrants though it appeals to tyrants very much. It is a resort, too, of people who are in the utmost good faith and are driven by the very intensity of their caring about some or other issue. It surfaces every time somebody seeks to prevent some line of research or to suppress some finding, on the grounds that the result may be, or the finding is ‘undesirable’.

However, as Galileo is reputed to have said, “It moves all the same”. Galileo had published the evidence for the belief that the Earth moves; specifically that it rotates on its axis and around the Sun. He was coerced by the Inquisition into retracting his statements and saying that he did not believe them. The story goes that after announcing his retraction he muttered under his breath, “It moves all the same.” And of course it did move all the same. It moved before Galileo published his findings, it was moving while he retracted them, and it has been moving ever since.

The point is, in George Orwell’s terms, nobody controls the present. The Inquisition could coerce Galileo but it could not coerce the Earth. A sufficiently powerful government could falsify data until everybody believed that blood-letting cures fever or that smallpox is prevented by eating garlic. Everybody might be induced to act on these beliefs, but the germs would not listen. People would die who would otherwise have lived and, what is more serious to the regime, more people would die than in other countries. If the government was not prepared to back down it would be forced either to cut off contact between its people and the rest of the world, so that they would not know how far they had been disadvantaged, or to try to impose its system on the rest of the world by force or fraud. There are numerous examples of both policies in history. Sometimes, as in the case of the Soviet Union, both were pursued at the same time.

We cannot create truth by agreement or deceit unless we are talking about truly arbitrary convention, like the rule of the road; but it is very unlikely that in any real instance we would be talking of these. Arbitrary conventions create no problems. The desire to suppress or distort or fabricate truth arises precisely where there is a truth to suppress or distort.

This fact matters very much. Once a regime, or a whole society, embarks on defending a myth that purports to be based on fact there is no knowing how far the harm will spread or what the cost will be. As we have already noticed, it can lead to cutting off contact with the rest of the world, with the necessary consequence of excluding all sorts of useful and harmless information along with that which is feared. It is likely that ever-widening spheres of enquiry will have to be prohibited so that the defence of the myth is not outflanked. Reality has the inconvenient character that ultimately everything links up with everything else; and there is no knowing in advance from what direction a particular set of ideas may be called in question.

Implications of New Theories

Finally, and most seriously of all, we can never know in advance how important a new theory or discovery may ultimately turn out to be. Those who persecuted Galileo no doubt believed that the scientific facts regarding the movement of the Earth were quite unimportant – it made no practical difference – whereas the Mediaeval view of the cosmos was of the utmost importance, underpinning the Christian religion and the conventions of moral behaviour that made civilised human life possible.

At that time both these beliefs were entirely plausible, but they both turned out to be wrong. The revolution in astronomical thinking of which Galileo’s work was a vital part led to the new understanding of motion which was formulated by Newton, and it was Newton’s laws of motion and the new understanding of mechanics which they opened up, that made possible the industrial revolution and the whole development of the modern world. On the other hand, the Christian religion turned out to be perfectly able to do without Mediaeval cosmography (of which the Twelve Apostles must have been entirely ignorant), and whatever we may think of the condition of morality and the conventions of civilised life in the modern world, they are certainly not in a worse state than they were in Renaissance Italy, the land of Pope Alexander VI and Cesare Borgia.

Great is the Truth, and it shall prevail.

Disclaimer: This essay was extracted from O’Dowd’s 1999 occasional paper, “Liberal Reflections”, for the Free Market Foundation. The essay’s name was changed from the original “All Being Wrong Together” and the headings were inserted by Rational Standard editors.

The post Protecting Truth from Willful Ignorance and Deceit appeared first on Rational Standard.

]]>
https://rationalstandard.com/protecting-truth-willful-ignorance-deceit/feed/ 0 6240